264. Giorgio Pini on Scotus on Knowledge

Posted on

Peter hears about Duns Scotus' epistemology from expert Giorgio Pini.

Transcript
download-icon
.

Themes:

Further Reading

• G. Pini, Categories and Logic in Duns Scotus: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Categories in the Late Thirteenth Century (Leiden: 2002).

• G. Pini, “Scotus on the Objects of Cognitive Acts,” Franciscan Studies 66 (2008), 281-315.

• G. Pini, “Scotus on Knowing and Naming Natural Kinds,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 26 (2009), 255-72.

• G. Pini, “Scotus on Doing Metaphysics in statu isto,” in M.B. Ingham and O. Bychkov (eds), John Duns Scotus, Philosopher (Munster: 2010), 29-55.

• G. Pini, “Can God Create my Thoughts? Scotus’s Case against the Causal Account of Intentionality,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 49 (2011), 39-63.

• G. Pini, “Scotus on Intuitive and Abstractive Cognition,” in J. Hause (ed.), Debates in Medieval Philosophy (London: 2014), 348-65.

• G. Pini, “Scotus’s Questions on the Metaphysics: A Vindication of Pure Intellect,” in F. Amerini and G. Galluzzo (eds), A Handbook to Commentaries on the Metaphysics in the Middle Ages (Leiden: 2014), 359-84.

• G. Pini, “Two Models of Thinking: Thomas Aquinas and John Duns Scotus on Occurrent Thoughts,” in G. Klima (ed), Intentionality, Cognition, and Mental Representation in the Medieval Philosophy (New York: 2015), 81-103.

Comments

Otter Bob on 8 November 2016

A Distaste for the Medievals?

I thought it best to wait until I had listened and reviewed all five episodes on Duns Scotus. Now I've got so many questions and problems that I'm having trouble keeping it all straight. But I'll limit my concerns, for now, to two issues in separate posts.

The first issue is the current negative attitudes towards the Medieval period. Two posts to Episode 263 refer to “this old crap” and “...how the culture of most science grads is to think that Medievals as some sort of people that checked their brain out the door for a few centuries.” I do understand that neither of these remarks are held to be true by the authors of the comments, and your (Peter's) replies are informative, persuasive and generous almost to a fault (“Maybe a matter of taste!”---perhaps with some irony).

Such prejudices are far from being just occasional. But what I think is a major undercurrent to all this is a view that the Christian, Jewish and Islamic philosophy of this time was so heavily dependent upon a certain theology. We moderns (present company excepted), being more high-browed (like giraffes) and living in a secular age, find all this “God-talk” as irrelevant and thus to be dismissed out of hand. To be a bit more precise: it's the Abrahamic notion of God as an individual substance (often with enhanced human traits), being the creator of all else and personally involved in the world which is thought to be repugnant and an obstacle to serious philosophical work. You have certainly shown us that the better thinkers of the so-called “Dark Ages” have much more refined and well-reasoned positions on the Divine and that they deserve more credit and attention than they receive today.

But this is how I want to phrase the issue: If we leave aside this appeal to God as a first principle of all that exists, with a nature from which we can draws inferences about how and why things are as they are, and who functions as the ultimate justification for certain positions---if we do that subtraction, is there any significantly new problems or intriguing discussions within Medieval thought that go beyond the investigations of the Classical Greek thinkers? Or is all this just commentaries, particularly on Aristotle? The Medieval thinkers certainly had their disagreements with the Ancients, who had their own disputes. But despite their fine intellects and subtle distinctions, do they represent, without the theology, anything more than “footnotes” to (to be bit more generous) the Greek philosophers?

Let me use Scotus for some examples of alleged important innovations.  Take his view of the univocity of Being and the other transcendentals, with God as the first principle of these (Ep. 260). Aristotle, of course, raised the issue of univocal versus equivocal terms and gave arguments for his position that “being” (and, I suspect, “good” and “one”) are equivocal terms—but equivocal in a certain way, namely pros hen, as you, explained in this episode and showed the linkage to the Medieval notion of analogy. Scotus, of course, differed from Aristotle. But his position on the univocity of Being doesn't seem to be that original. I thinking not only of Aristotle's consideration of it but also one interpretation of Parmenidean thought. Scotus' two arguments for univocity require a conception of God, so apart from such an appeal, I don't see much of a position at all without God.

Scotus has a new definition of possibility in that what is contingent is what implies no contradiction (Ep. 261). As you remark, the groundwork was laid by previous thinkers, e.g., Aristotle. I think it's debatable whether this is a truly new definition or even that it is coherent. But it's coherency is beside the point here. What I do note is your explanation of Scotus' three moments in the order of Nature (at about 14:50). Moments of what? I assume three moments of possibility. Or is it three moments of actuality or a mixture? You probably see here that I am referring back to the Aristotelian distinction between possibility and first and second actuality. With the (somewhat poor) example of a lion: we begin with the first possibility that a lion could exist (nothing self-contradictory). Then we have the second possibility or first actuality of a lion existing but as a young pup needing further development, but not the bestowal of additional new capacities for development. Finally comes the full actuality of a mature, healthy lion. Should I accuse Scotus of baldy stealing an idea here and twisting it to suit his purposes or have I done the twisting? No seeing a significant difference between his first and second moments, I may be misconstruing his position.

Trying to move on more quickly, I'll just note at least one of the antecedents to Scotus' Divine Command Theory (Ep. 262). Is this not the same issue as found in Plato's Euthyphro? Does God commmand us to do X because it is good or is X good because God so commands? Scotus plumps for the latter and so does Euthyphro, before Socrates goes to work.

The concept of common natures is another important theme in Scotus' thinking (Ep. 263). For my case that there is “nothing new under the sun”, I'll stick my neck out and suggest that Scotus is referring to nothing other than the differentia discussed in Plato and Aristotle (the specific differences that distinquish the species in one genus). Lord knows the Scholastics, including Scotus, went to town with this item almost ad naseum, and I'm hardly competent or foolish enough to get caught up in a comparison of the features of common natures versus differentia. So this is only a conjecture.

Enough!  I would enjoy going on to discuss the origins of the concepts of “thisness” and cognitive intuition in the Greek philosophers. But I'll rest my case and anticipate some fascinating examples of true innovation, independent of their theology, by the variety of thinkers in these later centuries. I've learned the lesson that I can get befuddled and blunder into some grand misinterpretations and self-demolishing analyses, so I'm not fully confident here. But I sure would appreciate some constructive criticism and suggestions as I continue my difficult but pleasurable investigations with these Islamic and Christian philosophers.

 

In reply to by Otter Bob

Peter Adamson on 8 November 2016

Originality of Scotus

Wow, that's a wonderful and very detailed response to the episodes, thank you. It strikes me that you're thinking about this in sufficient depth that you probably want to just go read up on Scotus and delve deeper, rather than getting more of my take on it. But, without getting into each invididual issue too deeply here, let me say generally that you are broadly right that Scotus is innovating within broad issues that are already in Plato and Aristotle. (Of course one could argue that the entire history of philosophy is pretty much only doing that!) So for example the Euthyphro dilemma is raised by Plato but explored with unprecedented detail (well, except maybe in Islamic theology) by Scotus. His is the first really sophisticated non-Islamic version of a divine command theory of ethics, which is nothing to sneeze at even if Plato, in a few lines, sketched out the possibility of such a position. Similarly, problems about the univocity of being are raised but not explored in nearly the same way by Aristotle: and by the way you don't actually need God to get into Scotus' position, since you could frame the whole thing as a question about whether the being of material substances and of their accidents is univocal or not, so limit the discussion only to that non-divine context.

So in general I think I would say Scotus makes dramatic leaps forward on several issues that had been around since antiquity, and also advances certain issues to the fore that had receded into the background somewhat. And his positions had often been anticipated, by Avicenna and others, but not defended with such detailed acuity. An exception might be his view on individuation: here I struggle to think of anyone who has really even put forward a position like his, though of course others had tried to solve the problem. His view on universals by contrast can be read pretty plausibly as a convincing reading of what Avicenna wanted to say.

Otter Bob on 8 November 2016

Limits to the Powers and Absolute Freedom of God?

[My second issue]

God cannot (according to Scotus):

Create actual properties that are not underlaid by some subject.

Create Secretariat, that famously winning horse, without him having the common nature of horseness.

Render a principle of inference, such as modus ponens, invalid.

Choose to make the Principle of Non-Contradiction false.

Make every being an intrinsically necessary being.

Even contemplate looking for advice to some objective independent set of ethical standards.

Create the essence of anything without first grasping it.

        Ep. 262, c. 6:20   Even the natures of things are, for him [Scotus], ultimately

        grounded in God's will. Before God creates giraffes, he first grasps their natures

       and so creates them in intelligible being.

Release us from the obligation to love Him.

Once he has laid down the contingent but consistent and coherent natural and moral order of the created world, decide that sex outside marriage is never permissible.

Allow us to be fully happy and blessed solely by attaining human natural virtue.

Create, do or think what it intrinsically repugnant, incompatible, self-contradictory.

Etc, Etc.

 

Whow!  Should we agree to lay such limitations on the divine? Who do we think we are? Such hubris is sure to lead to our downfall. Despite Scotus' fine arguments, let's just remove the last limitation and allow God Absolute Freedom and Power, period, full stop, with no qualifications. Shall we not say that God can think, do and create what is absolutely repugnant even though it is self-contradictory? After all, for we mortal and corrupted humans, the Divine is truly ineffable. To argue otherwise will require assuming that the Law of Non-Contradiction is necessarily true and that is part of the question.

Otter Bob on 10 November 2016

Thank you for the compliment.

Thank you for the compliment. I knew I was reaching a bit but, anticipating that you would respond, I hoped to draw others in. But yes, we are in broad agreement. We do stand on the shoulders of the giants, Plato and Aristotle, which phrase I thought originated from Newton having never looked up its lineage back to the 12th century. (For those interested, see Wikipedia: “Standing on the shoulders of giants”.) I will go and read up further on Scotus. But I also have that old problem with books: Upon questioning, they just say the same thing back. If I can talk to someone I respect and who will put up with me, I find that far superior.

Although Scotus often makes me feel all stuffy in the head (with distinctions), I would never sneeze at his thinking. But I bet those few lines of Plato have had an influence far beyond their length. For example, does this fundamental particle have a negative charge because it is an electron or is it an electron because it has a negative charge? Or, are the Marx brothers' movies funny because people laugh at them or do people laugh at them because they are funny? In each example are both ways of putting it true and true in the same way? (For other readers and if interested, see Ep. 216 and the exchange between Peter and I.)

I agree that Aristotle and Scotus come at the univocal/equivocal distinction in different ways and that you could get into the issue without invoking God in the way you suggest. I'm not sure Scotus could get to it that way, if he believes that infinite being is prior to limited being in reality as opposed to how we come to have a cognition of being. But I better be careful here, and that's not the issue anyway.

Could we satisfy Scotus by undoubling the double negative of Henry of Ghent's proposal? We could say in a positive way that an individual is one different (changing “not identical”) member from the members of the same species and it is a whole individual (changing “not divisible into further individuals”)? All we have to do is get past the difficulties with the various ways we speak of one, unity, singular, simple, same, different, and whole (being facetious).

Scotus uses the distinction between a genus and its different specific differences as an analogy for understanding how the haecceity (“total form of the individual” or “singular nature”) of a particular can explain both the 1) indivisibility of a particular into further particulars and 2) the individuality of a particular both a) in itself (especially over time) and b) from other particulars. If we again employ that Euthyphro type of question, we might ask: Is a particular thing an individual because it has a haecceity (thisness) or does it have a haecceity because it is an individual? Scotus, I believe, argues for the former. But I still don't believe in Scotus' haecceities as an additional feature of particulars. And I don't have the time either to wait for the next life nor have the surety of arriving so that I can grab hold onto a haecceity. But I do believe in “thisnesses” in that I can point out this identical twin Adamson versus that identical twin Adamson. So perhaps I can also, by intuitive cognition, grasp directly and immediately in the here and now the thisness of an individual. But neither an intuitive grasp nor an ostensively pointing will do any better than the totality of the individual's accidents (back to Gilbert of Poitier exactly one year and seven months ago to Ep. 216). I keep insisting that the being of a particular being is the fact that it is this some (kind of) thing or other. But darn it, that won't explain either the indivisibility or individuality of a particular. Maybe I don't believe in particulars any more, but then I am, as an individual, in trouble. Can I have time to think about all this (like the rest of my life or at least until we get to Ockham next year)?

I better get started and I'll take any help I can get. Thanks again.

In reply to by Otter Bob

Peter Adamson on 10 November 2016

More Scotus

I tend to agree about haecceities - just one thought though about your undoing the double negation of Henry's solution. I suspect what Scotus would say about that is basically what he says to Henry's version: if we say two particulars are different, rather than not the same, then we are just re-stating the fact that needs to be explained (i.e. that this rose is different from that rose), rather than explaining the fact.

Stoev on 31 December 2016

Intuitive and discursive knowledge

I am excited to understand that Kant's distinction between intuitive and discursive cognitive faculties can be traced back to Scotus.

Thanks for all these episodes on Scotus!

Xaratustra on 21 February 2017

Intuitiv knowledge

Hi Peter,

Thanks for the nice episodes on Scotus. In this last episode, similar to episode 242, the topic got very close to issues of self awareness, and I actually enjoyed very much Scotus' view on the intuitiv knowledge of certain things that do not need sense perception. Two questions come to my mind:

One is, if philosophers of the east ever got this far on this issue? (I was expecting that Avicenna got very close with his flying man).

Second is that I was wondering if any philosopher ever argued that this kind of intuitiv knowledge is actually not real, but rather an "emergent phenomenon". This may sound deeply "atheistic" and I am not sure if one can expect this from medieval philosophers to questions things so far. It would be interesting if someone did.

Many thanks

In reply to by Xaratustra

Peter Adamson on 22 February 2017

Intuitive knowledge

The answer to the first question is definitely yes - as you mention Avicenna is an example with the flying man but then there is "knowledge by presence" as covered in the episodes on Suhrawardi and the Illuminationists. Check out also Kaukua's book "Self-Awareness in Islamic Philosophy."

I'm not sure I understand the last question, though - usually people don't talk about knowledge as being emergent, but rather consciousness or mental phenomena in general. Could you elaborate?

In reply to by Peter Adamson

Xaratustra on 15 March 2017

Heap

Thanks for the reply. Just received the Kaukua's book, so I am eager to go through it. I am actually happy that I have meanwhile come further into the episodes on the Indian philosophy though. This would help me better explain my second point. Because what I actually mentioned in my question as the "self" being an "emergent phenomenon" seems to be similar to that of the Buddhist tradition (as compared to the concept of self in the Upanishads). Like you mention grains that make up a heap, the concept of self would "emerge" from nothing after there is enough substance? If I understood the Buddhist view correctly, then this would be the answer to my question, only wondering why philosophers of further west (including islamic world) ever had a go at this?

In reply to by Xaratustra

Peter Adamson on 19 March 2017

Emergentism

Actually if you wait for just a couple of episodes, in the India series we are about to get to Carvaka and they take exactly this view. In fact our episode is about whether they can be called "emergentists" regarding the mind and the answer is yes. The Buddhists would not agree: for them there is no enduring self or mind of course, there are only momentary mental events.

Add new comment

The content of this field is kept private and will not be shown publicly.
Transcript +

Note: this transcription was produced by automatic voice recognition software. It has been corrected by hand, but may still contain errors. We are very grateful to Tim Wittenborg for his production of the automated transcripts and for the efforts of a team of volunteer listeners who corrected the texts.

Peter Adamson: We're going to be focusing on Scotus's theory of cognition or knowledge. And in order to get at what's special about Scotus, I thought it would be a good idea to first ask you about his predecessors. Maybe we could focus on Aquinas because Aquinas is famous, and also Scotus responds to him quite extensively. What is the kind of basic idea that Aquinas would have about how we come to have knowledge of the world around us through our sense experience?

Giorgio Pini: Thomas Aquinas' idea was that we get knowledge of everyday objects, let's say a giraffe, by starting up with sensory properties. So for example, color of the giraffe, or the smell of the giraffe, all the things that we can get acquainted with by our senses. Then we develop that sort of information through our cognitive powers. So our sensory power, our memory and finally our mental powers. What do we get at the end of the story? Well, we get a concept of a giraffe that is for Aquinas a form that is present in our mind. And that form corresponds to the form of the giraffe out in the world. The two are very similar, even the same in some respects. For that reason, for Aquinas, we can get to the essence of things in the world - know what a giraffe is, starting with our senses and ending up with concepts in our mind.

Peter Adamson: And this concept would basically involve all of the essential properties of what a giraffe is. So there's nothing left out.

Giorgio Pini: Yes, there is nothing left out. Aquinas is aware that it may be very difficult and it may also take a long time to get all the essential properties - something that a biologist can do in many years. But he's pretty confident that it is something that we can do just relying on our senses and our cognitive powers.

Peter Adamson: What happens then after we die? Because Aquinas thinks that what happens in the beatific vision or when we get to heaven, as it were, is that our cognitive access to the truth improves quite a lot. And from what you just said, it sounds like there's not much room for improvement.

Giorgio Pini: Yeah. For Aquinas, basically the same pattern, the same kind of explanation works in the next life, of course with some sort of modification. In the next life we will not be acquainted with everyday material objects like a giraffe. Our knowledge will be of God, a very different kind of object. So in order to get the knowledge of God, we will not be able to rely on our senses clearly. At the same time, Aquinas is willing to keep the basics of his account of knowledge. And he says that we still have a form in our mind, a form of God, when we know God. The way we acquire it is not through our senses, but basically God himself will give us this form. The peculiar idea that Aquinas has is that in the case of the beatific vision of our knowledge of God in the next life, God will play the role both of the object, what we know, and of the form through which we know that object. So God will play two roles, so to speak.

Peter Adamson: As if God were both the giraffe and the image of the giraffe. So that's a very special case, obviously, but in general terms, he thinks that the cognitive mechanism is the same. You get a form.

Giorgio Pini: Exactly. You get a form through different channels: through the senses in the case of this life, directly from God in the next life. But the cognitive mechanism that is in us is basically the same, and it works in the same way. In a way, we can say that God has to adapt to it, because for us to know is just to have a form in our mind. So if God wants to be known by us, he has to play the role of the form as well - of this image.

Peter Adamson: And this is one of the things that Scotus is going to question and challenge, because he thinks there's a big difference between our knowledge in this life and our knowledge in the next life. To get into that, though, let's start with this life. What would Scotus say is happening when I look at a giraffe? So I'm at the zoo, there's the giraffe, what would he think happens?

Giorgio Pini: Well, on the one hand, he says something that is similar to what Aquinas says, because he thinks that I get acquainted with the giraffe, I know what a giraffe is, starting with the sensory information that I gather from the giraffe, starting from these sensory qualities. So again, the color, the smell, the noise that the giraffe can make in certain circumstances, this is the starting point, like for Aquinas. But then the way this information, the starting information is developed, is a little different for Scotus, because Scotus is very much aware of the problem. He thinks that what these sensory properties, like the smell, the color, the noise that a giraffe makes, what these kind of sensory properties give us is very little information, very, very little. If we think of the gap between the smell of a giraffe and the sophistication of a concept that a biologist has of what a giraffe is, there seems to be a long way to go. And there seems to be no way to just bridge this gap through making the information that is already present in the sensory qualities more and more sophisticated - through some sort of refinement. Scotus thinks that something more is required.

Peter Adamson: And how do I get to this something more? Because it seems like the only access I have to the world around me is through my senses.

Giorgio Pini: That's correct, the only access that I have to the world is through my senses. But we also have very powerful mental capacities of an inferential kind, so that we can make reasonings about the information that we gather through the senses. That was something that Aquinas as well, of course, was well aware of. But for Scotus, it is on these inferential capacities that we have really to focus in order to explain how we get from the sensory information to the more sophisticated concept that we have in our mind. How does the story work for Scotus? Well, again, I start with my direct acquaintance with the smell or with the color. Then I can get a concept of what a color is. But this is still a concept of a property. What a medieval thinker would call an "accident" is not what a giraffe is, what an object is. If we could rely on just our senses and on the development of what we get from our senses that we can carry out, we should stop here. How do we get to the concept of what a giraffe is? Well, at that point, our inferential powers come in and we realize - we reason actually, that if there are properties, there must be a subject underlying them. There must be something, an object that is not a property, but is the thing to which all these properties belong.

Peter Adamson: So you start with these accidents. So it's brown, it smells bad. Let's face it, giraffes are not the most fragrant beasts. It's tall, it's located in the zoo. And then you think, 'well, wait a minute, these accidents are all kind of happening in the same place. So it must be that there's something underneath, so to speak, to which they belong.'

Giorgio Pini: Precisely. Yes. And this is a piece of reasoning. This is not something that we can arrive at only by the information we get from the senses and by some sort of elaboration of that information.

Peter Adamson: And does he actually think that it's literally a conscious piece of reasoning that sort of goes through your mind explicitly? 'Oh, look, there must be something underneath.'

Giorgio Pini: Well, Scotus is not very clear about this, but I don't think that is the case. I think that Scotus thinks that just because our mind is built up in a certain way, it has the power, it is predisposed to work in that way when faced with some accidents. So I do not have to consciously think, 'oh, there is a smell, there is a color, they cannot just float, they do not just float around in reality, but they always come together. So there must be a subject to which they belong.' This is a piece of reasoning that I make sort of unconsciously, if you want, just because my mind is set up to work in that way.

Peter Adamson: Okay, but what if a skeptic came along and said, 'well, I don't believe there's anything underlying, I think that maybe there is a giraffe. But to me, a giraffe is nothing more than a kind of collection or bundle,' as sometimes is said in today's metaphysics - like a bundle theory of a substance. The idea would be that there's nothing more to the giraffe than being a bundle of these properties.

Giorgio Pini: Yes. Well, Scotus is in some ways aware of this possible criticism. So he actually has an argument to show that there must be something underlying, which is not a property, but is a subject of properties. His basic argument is that that is the best explanation to account for the fact that these different accidents, these different properties - a smell, a color, come together and this sort of 'bundle,' if you want, is constant over time. And some of these properties, some of these elements of the bundle can be lost, but other ones are retained and we still recognize some sort of very important identity over time. And that is his argument - that is the argument that he uses to show that there must be an underlying object, an underlying subject, behind these different properties.

Peter Adamson: That's interesting because it actually echoes something Aristotle says in the Categories where he's trying to explain what a substance is and he says a substance is the thing that undergoes change. So for example, human goes from being white to not-white, or from not-white to white. And so that idea of the underlying thing that persists through change, the idea that that's what it really means to be a substance seems to go all the way back to Aristotle.

Giorgio Pini: Absolutely, yes. Aristotle was definitely the main source for Scotus, even though Scotus, like many other scholastic thinkers, used Aristotle in a very inventive way. So for example, concerning this problem of the underlying object, as you said, there is definitely the idea of the Aristotelian substance underlying different changes. But Scotus adds a twist to this idea, if you want, because Scotus thinks that there is also a cognitive side to this story. So that he's talking about not just the structure of reality, the fact that there are underlying subjects, but he's also saying that, 'well, we can find out that there are underlying objects, that there are objects behind the smells, colors, because there is something that goes on over time and remains the same in some sense.' So an idea like that of a substance that started out like something purely metaphysical, if you want, something that tells us something about the way the world is. Now that same idea is being used by Scotus also to illustrate something about the way we know the world is.

Peter Adamson: Let me try a different kind of skeptical response to this theory. Instead of thinking of the substance as a bundle of properties, what if I said: okay, sure, there is something underlying these properties, but I couldn't possibly know what it is because of the way you just set it up, right? So you've told me my access to the world is through sense perception, all the things I get through sense perception are just accidental properties. It seems like the only thing left for the substance to be is an "I know not what," as Locke later will put it.

Giorgio Pini: Yes. Well, on the one hand, Scotus would agree that in this life, we can never have a complete grasp of what a thing is, as he says, a complete grasp of the essence of a thing. On the other hand, he's very confident that even though our grasp is sort of not completely detailed, we can still get a grasp of the essence of something. How can we do that? Well, the problem, as you indicated, is that we have to bridge the gap between properties and what this subject is. Scotus thinks that we can do that because the object underlying these properties is not something of a completely different kind from the properties that are present in that object. After all, we say both about the object and about the properties that they are 'some thing.' that may not be very informative, admittedly, but this is something that for Scotus is very, very important because he argues that if we say both about the object and about the properties that they are something, we must be using the word "something" in the same sense. That is what offers us a bridge between properties and object.

Peter Adamson: So this is referring to the so-called theory of the univocity of being. In other words, the idea that existence or being always means the same thing, whether it's God, an accident, or a substance - which is something I talked about in a recent episode. So the thought there, I guess, would be that: I do have access to accidents. I don't have immediate access to substances, but since substances are beings and accidents are beings, and since being is being because it's univocal, I've got access to something that's of the same type as the thing I really want access to, which is the substance.

Giorgio Pini: Precisely. So the idea is that, as you said, I start up with accidents, then I can form the concept of a being, of something, just out of the little information I get from accidents. Afterwards, after all, even if I am just acquainted with the color or with the smell, I can form the concept of something, of a being, out of that little piece of information that I have. Now that I have the concept of a being, I can make an inference and conclude that there must be something behind those properties, those colors, those smells. What do I know about that something? Admittedly, not very much, but at least I know that it is something in the very same sense of something in which properties, accidents, are something. And I know, of course, that that object is the subject of properties. So at least I have the basis on which I can build up a more and more sophisticated concept of what that thing is. The more information I gather, the more accidents I am acquainted with, the more things I can say about that object.

Peter Adamson: And I guess that also means that I can have a unified science, which is metaphysics, which studies all the beings, accidents, substances, and also God.

Giorgio Pini: Absolutely. So even though Scotus seems to have some sort of skeptical side in what he says, because he thinks that we do not have a direct access to the objects - to even material objects in this world, he is pretty confident that we can build up a science of being, a science of reality in this life. We can have a very solid metaphysics. And the tools by which we build up metaphysics for Scotus are basically two. The first one is the univocal concept of being about which we have just been talking about. Because we have this univocal concept, we can move from our acquaintance of accidents and derive that knowledge of objects. The second tool is our inferential capacities. Scotus argues that we can trust our inferential capacities completely. So for example, we can trust completely the principle of non-contradiction and we can trust completely our capacities to derive consequences from a premise. That is the other way by which, even though I do not have a direct grasp of what a giraffe is - I'm not plugged in to the essence of a giraffe directly, I can arrive at a pretty sophisticated and complex concept of what a giraffe is by saying, first of all, 'a giraffe is an object. Second, it is an object which is the subject of such and such and such properties.'

Peter Adamson: You keep saying "in this life" as a kind of caveat, which implies that things will be different in the next life. We said before, regarding Aquinas, that Aquinas has the idea that cognition will work in the same basic way in this life and in the afterlife. I take it that for Scotus that is not true, so does that mean that in the afterlife I just am plugged in to the essence of giraffe, as you put it? That sounds like paradise to me.

Giorgio Pini: Well, in a way, yes, that's definitely the case. That's the other important difference between Scotus and Aquinas concerning the theory of cognition. In the next life, we will not rely anymore on our senses, clearly. We will not need to make this sometimes complicated inference starting with the senses arriving at the notion of an object underlying the accidental properties. In the next life, we will make use of a special power that we already have in this life, but because of the limitation - our cognitive limitations in this life, we do not use now. This special cognitive power that we have is what Scotus calls intuitive cognition, which is a power to have direct access to the essence of something without all the mediation of the senses of inferential powers that are necessary right now.

Peter Adamson: And this intuitive kind of knowledge, can I have that at all during this life? I mean, is there anything I have intuitive access to?

Giorgio Pini: Yeah, that is actually a controversial point for scholars of Scotus, but Scotus is pretty clear that in this life, there are some cases in which we have this intuitive knowledge of things. So that is also evidence that we are able to have it in the next life because there are a few cases, which are pretty uncontroversial for Scotus, in which we have this intuitive direct grasp of the essence of something in this life. Examples are our own cognitive faculties and possibly even our own mind. How do we know our own cognitive faculties? Well, clearly not through sensory accidents because cognitive faculties are not things that have sensory accidents.

Peter Adamson: Like I don't smell myself thinking or...

Giorgio Pini: Exactly. I don't smell myself thinking. But I do know that I think. How do I know? Well, according to Scotus, because I have a sort of direct access to my power of thinking and that direct access is this cognitive knowledge.

Peter Adamson: Right. So the way that I would access what a giraffe is in the afterlife is the way that I access the fact that I'm thinking about giraffes right now.

Giorgio Pini: Yes. There is a little complication about that because in the next life, the main object of knowledge will be God. And God is an object important enough to be basically the main, if not the only, object of knowledge in the next life. But I will know God through this intuitive knowledge directly without any mediation. So no need of a 'form of God' as Aquinas had thought. And by knowing the essence of God directly, I will also know in a sort of secondary way, but very powerful way, all the essences of the other things because all the essences of the other things are contained in some way in God.

Peter Adamson: So I do get the giraffes after all. That's all I care about.

Giorgio Pini: Absolutely. And in a much better way than I can get the giraffe in this life.

Peter Adamson: Just out of curiosity, this very heavy restriction on our intuitive knowledge in this life, is that a punishment for The Fall or is it just because we're embodied or both? Or is it not clear?

Giorgio Pini: It is not clear in the sense that Scotus takes into account both the possibilities that you mentioned. He says that it may be due just to The Fall as a sort of a punishment for The Fall, maybe now we have to get the essence of things in a roundabout way through the senses, through inferences. We are not able to do it directly anymore. And in only a few cases like the knowledge of our own cognitive powers, or even of our volitions, we can do that in a direct way. So this could be a consequence of The Fall or it could just be the fact that we are embodied beings - that we have a body. And so God decided maybe to harmonize our body and our minds. And he decided just to create things in such a way that to my power to get knowledge of things, there corresponds my power to get knowledge of sensory accidents through the senses. Scotus doesn't have a definitive view about this, but it's pretty clear that this is a contingent situation. This is true just in this life. And it is also quite clear that for Scotus, this is a cognitive limitation. So the senses are very useful in this life because they are the only door through which I can get access to objects, to material objects. But they are also a very limiting kind of door because they do not give us a direct access to the essence of things. In the next life we do not need that kind of limiting channel. We can get access to the essences of things in that sort of direct way.

Peter Adamson: One last question, speaking of the afterlife, let me ask you something about Scotus's afterlife in the historical tradition. A lot of the things you've said, for me, ring bells with people like Descartes or Hume. So for example, the idea that we have some kind of immediate access to the fact that we're thinking sounds a lot like Descartes' famous Cogito argument. The idea that we only get access to material substances through the kind of sense impressions they make on us sounds like Hume and the other empiricists. Is that just a coincidence, or is there a historical link between Scotus and these early modern thinkers?

Giorgio Pini: No, I don't think it is a coincidence. Of course, there are many differences between Scotus and these early modern thinkers. For example, as I said, Scotus was never a skeptic and never even went through a stage of skepticism because he always had full confidence in our inferential capacities and in our ability to make up a univocal concept of what something is. Also, for Scotus, sensory properties are not just in my mind. They are out there in the world. They are objective features of the world. And that is quite an important difference between Scotus on the one hand, and I would say all late medieval thinkers on the one hand, or most of them, and early modern thinkers. At the same time, there are indeed some striking similarities. And that is not a coincidence because Scotus had a very strong influence on many people thinking and writing after him. More specifically, he had a very strong influence on people writing textbooks of metaphysics or on cognition. For example, like Francisco Suarez, for example, a Spanish thinker active in the 16th century who wrote an entire system of philosophy. Suarez was heavily influenced by Thomas Aquinas, but he was also heavily influenced by Scotus. Actually, we can say that he read Aquinas through Scotus. Suarez, in turn, was influencing a tradition of textbooks that were the sort of textbooks with which, for example, Descartes was familiar with when he studied in the Jesuit college. He was given access to these kind of textbooks. So in this way, even though it is in an indirect way, I think that it is correct to say that Scotus had an influence on early modern thought.