179 - Mohammed Rustom on Philosophical Sufism

Posted on

Peter is joined by Mohammed Rustom in a discussion about Sufi authors including Ibn 'Arabī, al-Qūnawī, and Rūmī.

Transcript
download-icon
.

Themes:

Further Reading

• M. Rustom, “Is Ibn al-'Arabī’s Ontology Pantheistic?” Journal of Islamic Philosophy 2 (2006), 53-67.

• M. Rustom, “Approaches to Proximity and Distance in Early Sufism,” Mystics Quarterly 33 (2007), 1-25.

• M. Rustom, “The Metaphysics of the Heart in the Sufi Doctrine of Rumi.” Studies in Religion 37 (2008), 3-14.

• M. Rustom, The Triumph of Mercy: Philosophy and Scripture in Mullā Ṣadrā (Albany: 2012).

• M. Rustom (ed.), W.C. Chittick, In Search of the Lost Heart: Explorations in Islamic Thought (Albany: 2012).

• M. Rustom, “Ibn 'Arabī’s Letter to Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī: a Study and Translation.” Oxford Journal of Islamic Studies 25 (2014).

Prof. Rustom's webpage with lots of resources on the Islamic intellectual tradition.

Comments

Peter Adamson on 8 June 2014

Sound quality again

Just to say that this interview was recorded over Skype so the sound quality is not up to the usual standard on interviews - but it isn't too bad.

In reply to by Peter Adamson

Zsolt on 15 December 2021

Lofi_Sufi

No worries. I found that playing a lofi backtrack goes perfectly with the compressed audio vibe. I recommend it wholeheartedly :)

ROMAN PRYCHIDKO on 12 June 2014

The beautiful game

Hi Peter

Sufist philosophy in the premier league
Challenging for the championship of belief
Defended stoutly by al-Quwaui
Inspirational poetical play by Rumi

The beautiful game
Gods essence the frame
Impregnated with divine goals
A cosmic shape with interchangeable roles

Denis McAuley on 13 June 2014

Abd al-Qadir al-Jaza'iri?

First, the fan mail: I've been a keen listener since Plotinus, and I've enjoyed it all (in fact, having something good to listen to is the only thing that's brought me back to the gym, albeit intermittently).

Here's my question: after hearing you discuss Ibn Arabi's legacy with Professor Rustom, I was wondering if you had any plans to discuss Abd al-Qadir al-Jaza'iri (a.k.a. Emir Abdelkader) when the time comes. He's someone who engaged creatively with Ibn Arabi's ideas, and his life encapsulates a lot of the history of his period (he fought the French, ended up in late Ottoman Damascus, and posthumously became a nationalist icon).

In reply to by Denis McAuley

Peter Adamson on 13 June 2014

Abd al-Qahir

That's an interesting suggestion, thanks! I don't know if I will squeeze him in because the 19th c episode is a bit crowded (I wanted to get in later developments in the Ottoman realm, Iran and India). I'll see if I can fit him though.

Bernard Colbert on 1 July 2014

Mathematicians and Platonism.

I found this interview particularly fascinating, as I think that the way Dr Rustom described Ibn Arabi's approach to the Names of God as being very much the same as Mathematicians approach Mathematical objects.

Mathematicians often get the rough end of the stick. For example Leon Horsten writes in his article of the Philosophy of Mathematics in the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (http://stanford.library.usyd.edu.au/entries/philosophy-mathematics/):


Bernays observed that when a mathematician is at work she “naively” treats the objects she is dealing with in a platonistic way. Every working mathematician, he says, is a platonist (Bernays 1935). But when the mathematician is caught off duty by a philosopher who quizzes her about her ontological commitments, she is apt to shuffle her feet and withdraw to a vaguely non-platonistic position. This has been taken by some to indicate that there is something wrong with philosophical questions about the nature of mathematical objects and of mathematical knowledge.

I think the confusion comes due to the following types of exchanges between a Philosopher (P) and a Mathematician (M) - yes, it is a simplification and probably a little unfair to Philosophers.

P: So, are Mathematical objects just social conventions?
M: Umm, No.
P: So thinks like numbers are real?
M: Yes.
P: Can you show me one, like the number "three".
M: No - it is an abstract concept.
P: So it isn't material.
M: Correct.
P: It must be therefore an ideal form.
M: Sort of... (shuffles feet)
P: You are therefore a Platonist!!
M: If you say so

However, many Mathematicians (including myself) are Mathematical Realists, without being Platonists. Mathematicians do not consider Mathematical objects, such as number of Geometric figures, as having an ontological existence such as giraffes or Buster Keaton movies, but having an existance as relationships.

So I found Dr Rustom's explanation particularly useful.

In reply to by Bernard Colbert

Peter Adamson on 2 July 2014

Mathematical objects

Thanks, that's a very interesting and unexpected connection. I agree that the forced choice between full-blown Godel style realism and conceptualism is a false dichotomy that is often forced, not just on mathematicians, but on people who want to believe in other abstract objects (minds, universals, etc). Can you say a bit more about your solution though? I mean, if mathematical objects, like numbers, are relations, what are the relata? Like, if the number 4 is a relation, then it is a relation between two other things X and Y: what are X and Y?

In reply to by Peter Adamson

Bernard Colbert on 4 July 2014

Number

Yes - I agree that anyone postulating abstract objects has the same difficulty. I consider that the Mathematical objects I work with are real: and I am in the fortunate position of having some of thme realised in the form of ciphers.

The question you pose about the relationship of numbers to each other is probably the most difficult of questions to answer. My initial thoughts concerned geometric objects such as triangles and circles. These are essentially descriptions of relationships - and then by focussing on the relationship at an abstract level one can derive true statements about those relationships. Most Mathematical statements are of the form: If x then y.

As for number - the Mathematician Leopold Kronecker (1823-1891 see: http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/history/Biographies/Kronecker.html for biography) said "God created the integers, all else is the work of man."; the integers being whole numbers greater than 0.

There a several ways in which numbers can be thought of, and contructed. However, contructing them ex nihilo is a little difficult.

The Intuitionism of Brouwer asserts that all Mathematical objects are constructions - the the integer 4 has as relationship to the prior construction. This leads to a reduction to the first object, which is usually unity or 1. This approach, however, recognises that real Mathematicians are finite

In the 20th century, the construction of the integers was also derived from set theory - as is done in Whitehead et al. "Principia Mathematica". In this, one starts the the null set {}, i.e. nothing. Then one has the set of the null set: thus, one associated the set of the null set with the number 1 - since it has one element. Then a set can be constructed of the null set and the set of the null set, which has 2 elements. This is associated with the number 2. This process can be repeated for all the integers. In this case, 4 stands in relation to 3 as being derived from 3, and 5 as producing 5 in the next step.

Even in Ancient Greece there is something of this type of construction. Numbers were represented by lengths, which could be arbitrary: 2 was simply 1 added to itself. Multiplication was the area defined by a rectangle defined by the lengths of the size of the numbers. The Greek Mathematicians were able to develop a rich understanding of numbers.

What these approaches have in common is that the focus on relationships between the numbers: they also all suffer from the problem of starting from nothing, and being a little weak at that point.

I will have to read Ibn 'Arabī to work out if he is able to assist at this point.

In reply to by Bernard Colbert

Peter Adamson on 5 July 2014

Starting from nothing

Thanks - my philosophy of maths isn't good enough to build on what you're saying, but I would add two thoughts. First, you may like Eriugena, too. He is an early medieval thinker who explicitly says that God's creating things "from nothing (ex nihilo)" means creating them "from Himself" since He is nothing, in the sense of beyond being. We might even get to Eriugena before the end of the year since he'll be early in the medieval episodes.

Second, I like your point that math is mostly about hypothetical reasoning: if X then Y. I actually think philosophy is like that too, a lot of the time. That is, philosophers think about what would follow if one were to make a certain assertion: what objections could arise, or what else might follow from it? So for instance what are the implications (or costs and benefits) of a certain view of free will, say, or for that matter of the status of numbers.

 

Chike Jeffers on 1 July 2014

Chinese connection

I found the part about Chinese attempts to explain Ibn 'Arabi with the help of Confucianism fascinating. Prof. Rustom spoke about how it's only very recently that work has been done on this. Where might some of this work have been published?

In reply to by Chike Jeffers

Mohammed Rustom on 3 July 2014

Re: Chinese connection

Dear Chike,

The first place to look would be Sachiko Murata's "Chinese Gleams of Sufi Light", as well as "The Sage Learning of Liu Zhi: Islamic Thought in Confucian Terms" by Murata, William Chittick, and Tu Weiming.

"Rectifying God's Name: Liu Zhi's Confucian Translation of Monotheism and Islamic Law" by James Frankel is also a very useful study.

For the wider historical and cultural context, see "The Dao of Muhammad: A Cultural History of Muslims in Late Imperial China" by Zvi Ben-Dor Benite.

Kristian Petersen's website gives access to his articles on Chinese Sufism, and also includes information about his fascinating forthcoming books on the topic: http://drkristianpetersen.com/

It is interesting to note that it was not only the school of Ibn 'Arabi that played an important role in Chinese-language Islam. Sunni rational theology was also made available in Chinese. In "The Sage Learning of Liu Zhi", the authors demonstrate how important the fourteenth-century Ash'arite theologian 'Adud al-Din Iji's "al-Mawaqif fi 'ilm al-kalam" was for Chinese Muslim scholars, particularly the seventeenth-century author Liu Zhi. Liu calls Iji's book "Gezhi quanjing" ("The Complete Classic of Investigating and Extending"), and draws on Iji's discussions on cosmology quite a bit.

(Incidentally, select English translations from Iji's "Mawaqif", along with translations from Sayyid Sharif Jurjani's commentary upon this text, can be found in volume 3 of "An Anthology of Philosophy in Persia", edited by Seyyed Hossein Nasr and Mehdi Aminrazavi).

Hope these leads help.

Mohammed

In reply to by Mohammed Rustom

Chike Jeffers on 14 July 2014

Thanks very much!

I greatly appreciate the references.

James Ryman Bierly on 2 October 2014

Relational Names?

If the Divine Names are relational, then what are they a relationship between? From what I've read of Ibn Arabi, I'm thinking the answer is something like "non-being" and "God." Would that be accurate, or am I misunderstanding something here?

Also, if the divine names are manifest in the cosmos, then it seems that Arabi has a radically relational and transient view towards the created universe, something akin to the Buddhist Sunyata or modern process theology. Everything is changing and flowing relationship, rather than static ontological entities, formed out of the different possible relationships between Absolute Being and Absolute Nonbeing. Am I reading this correctly or not?

In reply to by James Ryman Bierly

Mohammed Rustom on 2 October 2014

Re: Relational Names

Hello Ryan,

The divine names obtain their relational status by virtue of God’s manifest “face” as it “looks toward” the fixed entities. Insofar as the fixed entities (which are nothing other than the quiddities in philosophical parlance) are “nonexistent” (think of the various debates on the status of quiddities), yes, the divine names are relationships between God and non-being. But, Ibn ‘Arabi (and his followers) insist that the fixed entities do have some kind of reality as they are nothing other than God’s objects of knowledge whose status of fixity in God’s “mind” never change, whether they are brought into concrete existence or not. When they are brought into concrete existence, divine names obtain. That is, the divine names are relationships between God qua manifestation and the objects of His knowledge qua concretization. This is explained in greater detail in my article, “Philosophical Sufism” in “The Routledge Companion to Islamic Philosophy” edited by Richard Taylor and Luis Xavier López-Farjeat.

Yes, it can be said that Ibn ‘Arabi has a radically relational and transient view towards the cosmos. But, the point to keep in mind, as he makes very clear, is that the divine names, although not ontological entities as such, are “real” insofar as their traces and effects are found throughout the cosmic order (which his everywhere, and in everything). Look at, say, a person who is called “sister,” “daughter,” and “teacher” all at the same time. These different names of hers obtain in accordance with the different people with whom she is associated (i.e., sibling, parent, and student respectively). Nobody would say that the name “sister” insofar as she has a sibling is an untrue or unreal designation. It is a name that comes about as a purely relational thing, but that name also designates a concrete fact and reality vis-à-vis this person’s association with her sibling.

With respect to the change and flow of things in the cosmic picture, indeed Ibn ‘Arabi does have a rather transient view of things from one perspective. But things get immediately complicated when we throw into the equation his views concerning (1) the “fixity” of the fixed entities in the cosmic order and (2) the renewal of creation at each instant (Chittick’s “The Sufi Path of Knowledge” is the best single book to consult for copious texts from Ibn ‘Arabi’s writings on both of these points). The thinker who is commonly associated with the flow-like nature of reality is Mulla Sadra, who was heavily influenced by Ibn ‘Arabi and his followers, but who ultimately presents a unique perspective on this and many other issues, in keeping with his ontology of the primacy of being.

Xaratustra on 11 September 2016

Qaysari

Hi Peter,

in this episode at some point the name Qaysari was mentioned apparently “Davod Qaysari” who has written a commentary on Ibn-Arabi’s Ringstones of Wisdom. Just in the spirit of without any gaps, are there any more info on him?

 

In reply to by Xaratustra

Mohammed Rustom on 11 September 2016

Re: Qaysari

Hi there!

Yes,  Dawud al-Qaysari was a major commentator upon Ibn 'Arabi's "Ringstones of Wisdom," and his introduction to this commentary has always been a major teaching text in Iran. There are some useful materials on Qaysari out there (both published and forthcoming). Here are some of them in no particular order:

1. A forthcoming introduction to his thought by Muhammad Faruque as part of the Islamic Texts Society's Scholars and Sages of Islam series: "Dawud al-Qaysari: The Mystery of Existence."

2. An entire translation and Arabic edition of the aforementioned introduction by Qaysari forthcoming by Mukhtar Ali (with Brill, I believe). It is a useful work, with a most helpful introduction and commentary.

3. An article on Qaysari here: http://www.mohammedrustom.com/wp-content/uploads/2013/05/Dawud-al-Qaysa…

4. Caner Dagli's groundbreaking book "Ibn al-'Arabi and Islamic Intellectual Culture", which gives good coverage to Qaysari and the main figures in the school of Ibn 'Arabi.

5. A useful book on him in French by Mehmet Bayrakdar, "La philosophie mystique chez Dawud de Kayseri" (Ankara, 1990).

 

Paul on 23 July 2017

Ibn Arabi a Pomo?

I'm interested by this point that Rustom makes about Ibn Arabi being viewed of as sort of a post-modernist It made me think back once of this American man, the son of a humanities professor, who ended up travelling across North Africa with traditional Muslim scholars. In an interview in the 90s he described Islam as "radically post-modern". Obviously, Ibn Arabi was, and is, a colossal figure especially for the old Muslim literati, and he remains influential in traditional circles in North Africa. That multiple people may have potentially arrived at simmilar conclusions seemingly independently might at to the validity of such a comparison. But exactly what, apart from frustratingly difficult prose, makes Ibn Arabi a post-modernist? Who are these scholars who claim Ibn Arabi as a postmodernist? And what are the similarities between Ibn Arabi's themes and the work of 'post-modernists'? It doesn't help that trying to define post-modernism is like trying to nail jelly to a wall, it's become a pop slur for nearly every 'continental' philosopher and virtually all of the big names associated with it reject the label. So what do we even mean when we say that Ibn Arabi is a 'proto-post-modernist'?

 

In reply to by Paul

Peter Adamson on 25 July 2017

Proto-post-modernist

Now that's a good question. I think when you add my knowledge of postmodern thought to my knowledge of Ibn ʿArabī the result may not be enough to give you a good answer, but perhaps it is because he has the idea that reality is a play of signifiers or of language, i.e. the divine names?
 

In reply to by Peter Adamson

Mohammed Rustom on 6 August 2017

Ibn 'Arabi and Post-Modernism

Dear colleagues,

Thought I would weigh in on the question of Ibn 'Arabi and postmodernism. Ibn 'Arabi should NOT be considered a postmodernist, and this for a number of reasons. The main one is that he believes in an objective truth, and proceeds on these grounds in all of his inquiries. With respect to the divine names, for Ibn 'Arabi they are relational and thus not ontological realities as such. At the same time, Ibn 'Arabi maintains that their effects are real, and describes the cosmos as nothing but traces of the divine names. When it comes to Ibn 'Arabi's hermeneutics, he has a wide-ranging view of scripture and legal theory, but is also very clear on the objective "rules" for engagement with both. For his hermeneutics, see the unparalleled study by Michel Chodkiewicz, "An Ocean Without Shore."

Some attempts have been made to reconcile Ibn 'Arabi with postmodernism. The most noteworthy attempt in this regard is Ian Almond's "Sufism and Deconstruction," which is a study of Ibn 'Arabi and Derrida. Although there are some great merits to this work, there are also fundamental problems in the author's interpretation of Ibn 'Arabi (both with respect to his Arabic prose and his ideas proper). One strong rebuttal to Almond's findings is by Atif Khalil, which is to be published in an upcoming issue of "Sacred Web."

Hope this helps!

Mohammed

 

Add new comment

The content of this field is kept private and will not be shown publicly.
Transcript +

Note: this transcription was produced by automatic voice recognition software. It has been corrected by hand, but may still contain errors. We are very grateful to Tim Wittenborg for his production of the automated transcripts and for the efforts of a team of volunteer listeners who corrected the texts.


PA: Today's episode will be an interview about philosophical Sufism with Mohammed Rustom, who is Associate Professor of Islamic Studies at Carleton University. So I guess the obvious first question here is, what do we mean when we talk about "philosophical Sufism"? Obviously, it must have some relationship to philosophy on the one hand and Sufism on the other hand, but I suppose maybe it is a more specific idea than Sufism in general, it is some specifically philosophical kind of Sufism. Is that the idea? 

MR: Yes. Well, the term "philosophical Sufism" is somewhat problematic because it can take in Sufis or Muslim mystics who are well-trained in the formal discipline of philosophy, and as well as philosophical theology in the later period. And it can also relate to authors who had a penchant for philosophical modes of expression, but who were not really philosophers in any way at all. So with that in mind, we can kind of say that philosophical Sufism broadly refers to the theoretical or doctrinal attempt on the part of Sufis to articulate some of these more central topics in Islamic thought pertaining to things like cosmology, ontology, theology, so on and so forth, but within the framework of what we can call their spiritual vision. This means that at minimum we encounter in philosophical Sufism a more concrete kind of articulation of any given abstract philosophical or theological problem or position. 

While it is true that philosophical Sufism and philosophy are conceived here from one perspective as two sides of the same coin, I would not wish to indulge in the simplistic characterization that we sometimes find that says that philosophical Sufism is simply philosophy clothed up in mythic form or symbolic garb or something like that. Philosophical Sufism presents itself by virtue of its emphasis on the lived and concrete understanding of revelation as, if you like, a kind of improved version of philosophy or philosophical theology, but one in which the philosophical vision and revelation are kind of complementary and articulated in something like a highly symbolic form. 

Now, often philosophical Sufism refers to the school of Ibn ʿArabī in particular, so there's that added nuance there. And this is because an increasingly systematic and more philosophical understanding of Ibn ʿArabī's own teachings eventually come to take center stage in the writings of his followers, particularly Qūnawī, who was, of course, his stepson and his most important direct disciple. Thus the term "school of Ibn ʿArabī" describes a particular approach largely colored by the thought of Ibn ʿArabī himself to the major philosophical and religious issues which confronted medieval Islamic thought. 3.30 But it should also be noted that the term normally used in Arabic and Persian to characterize the perspective of Ibn ʿArabī on the one hand, but also kind of philosophical Sufism more generally, is 'irfān naẓarī, or in Persian ʿirfān-i naẓarī, which is normally translated as something like "theoretical Sufism" or even "speculative Sufism", I guess, would work. This is a fairly helpful designation in terms of what's happened in philosophical Sufism, conceived in the widest possible sense, but with the caveat that by the term "theoretical Sufism" we mean here the wedding of philosophical activity and lived practical aspect of Islamic spirituality. There are thus, if you like, no armchair philosophical Sufis in classical Islamic civilization, if you will. 

4.20 

PA: So it sounds like in a way we could think about philosophical Sufism either as part of the history of philosophy in the Islamic world or as part of the history of Sufism in the Islamic world, and either one would be legitimate. 

MR: Yes, on one level this is correct, especially as we move further into the East and down the historical unfolding of the Islamic intellectual tradition, where the lines start to get blurred in so many different places. Philosophers of, you know, Aristotelian kind of peripatetic bent now writing as illuminationists on the one hand and then engaging people like Rūmī and Ibn ʿArabī on the other hand. So that kind of ambiguity, I think, that you're drawing on, or the kind of universal applicability of this term, really it is kind of symptomatic of the more eclectic nature of the Islamic intellectual tradition in the post-Avicennan phase of Islamic history. 

PA: So you've already mentioned in passing the most important figure in history of philosophical Sufism and maybe the second most important, Ibn ʿArabī and his follower Qūnawī. Do you think it would be fair to say that Ibn ʿArabī was the first philosophical Sufi or the first to do philosophy within Sufism? 

MR: I would not say that. On the one hand, as the tradition develops later, it is, of course, greatly indebted to him. But, you know, we find that Ibn ʿArabī is really following an intellectual trend within Sufism that largely was made popular probably by Ghazālī's time, especially by Ghazālī, in which of course a greater attention is paid to issues in cosmology and ontology primarily, but now within the framework of Sufi discourse. So one of the key figures in the integration of philosophy and Sufism, someone who was actually like a younger Andalusian contemporary of Ibn ʿArabī, is Ibn Sab'īn, who was much better trained actually than Ibn ʿArabī in the formal discipline of philosophy. 

Probably the single figure who was the most pivotal in terms of the harmonization of philosophy and Sufism and when we can really start speaking about a kind of philosophical Sufism as such, is that the great Persian Sufi martyr ʿAyn al-Quḍāt Hamadānī, who died in 1131 of the common era, and who was put to death by the Seljuk government at the age of 33 ostensibly on charges of heresy. Not only was 'Ayn al-Quḍāt important because he was the student of Aḥmad Ghazālī, Ghazālī's famous younger brother, who himself was a major figure in the Persian world, but he was also very well-read in Avicenna and of course in Ghazālī himself. He thus brings together over a century before Ibn ʿArabī two really important strands in Islamic thought, kind of like a careful synthesis between philosophy, theology, mysticism in a manner which is more explicit than Ghazālī in terms of his reliance on philosophy, but which conscientiously seeks to address certain perceived limitations in Avicenna because of his noncommittal stance on mysticism. So ʿAyn al-Quḍāt kind of stands as a seriously overlooked figure in this later Islamic intellectual tradition, as someone who, you know, for the first time articulates a number of concepts that would become kind of stock expressions and ideas in both Persian and Arabic language Sufism. 7.45 

For example, you have the concept of "Muhammadan Reality", the ḥaqīqa Muḥammadiyya, which after ʿAyn al-Quḍāt, as far as I could see, and particularly actually in Ibn ʿArabī and his followers, it really takes center stage, but the idea we find in ʿAyn al-Quḍāt explicitly, the Muhammadan Reality is identified with the First Intellect of Neoplatonic Islamic cosmology, there is in fact some kind of indication in ʿAyn al-Quḍāt's main theoretical work in Arabic. He wrote pretty much all of his works in Persian, but he has one Arabic book called Zubdat al-ḥaqāʾiq, or the Quintessence of Reality. And if we read between the lines there, it seems that even if Ibn ʿArabī's most unique doctrine of the nature of the divine names may have, at least in part, been influenced by ʿAyn al-Quḍāt, but that whole question remains to be answered in further investigation. 8.40 

PA: Okay, that is really interesting. So it sounds like Ibn ʿArabī is not coming out of a void in terms of the effort to integrate philosophy with Sufism. He's rather responding to something that was already an ongoing process. 

MR: Yes. 

PA: And I think it is also interesting, by the way, that Avicenna was already central at this very early stage of philosophical Sufism. And that is something we'll see carrying on through the later Sufi tradition. 

MR: Yes, indeed. 

PA: So to what extent would you say that Ibn ʿArabī is actually doing philosophy in a systematic way? I mean, I've covered him already, right? So there's clearly a lot of philosophical ideas in Ibn ʿArabī, but he writes these incredibly long sprawling discussions of all sorts of things, right? And really, from what I've read, it seems like usually attempts to cobble together a philosophical system from Ibn ʿArabī have to take texts from here and there, bring them together, and then do quite a lot of interpretation. 

MR: Right. 9.45 

PA: So is that unfair, or do you think that is basically right, that he's not a systematic thinker, but that he has philosophically interesting things to say unsystematically? 

MR: Yeah, I think that is actually an excellent characterization. What makes Ibn ʿArabī, of course, so interesting is that, as you've noticed, I'm sure, in reading him, one of the things that jumps out is that there isn't a direct kind of engagement with the discipline of philosophy. In fact, we don't even have a record of him ever having read Islamic philosophy. I mean, he never mentions Avicenna, for example, explicitly. But as you've demonstrated in your previous podcast, Ibn ʿArabī says that he met Averroes and his writings do evince on one level a deep familiarity with a host of philosophical terms and concepts. But, you know, the likeliest place Ibn ʿArabī would have learned of these was through his formal training in Kalām or philosophical theology. Of course, he was very well versed in Mu'tazilite and Asha'rite thought. And given the fact that that is not such a surprise anyway, because Islamic theology was thoroughly Avicenna-ized by Ibn ʿArabī's time, we're just not surprised that, you know, his ontology, its broad outlines, is even quite Avicennan. That was standard fare in Islamic theology by Ibn ʿArabī's time, of course. 

So Ibn ʿArabī is not technically speaking a systematic thinker, so you're correct definitely to say that. And I would say that he's not systematic in that he does not try to, like, fit things neatly into an order and worldview. He will continuously, refine his position, he'll affirm concepts from one different and even antithetical angle on one point, and then he'll go on later to deny it from another point. In fact, this is one of the reasons why Ibn ʿArabī in early modern scholarship was characterized as a madman. And even today you will have people call him, I remember, at least one book has been written which tries to demonstrate how Ibn ʿArabī was kind of like a proto-postmodernist. 11.45 

Of course, there is a certain degree of coherence in Ibn ʿArabī's worldview as well. I wouldn't say a certain degree, I would actually say a great degree of coherence. But it is far from being systematic in any real sense of the term. I mean, sometimes in the middle of a sentence in one of his books he'll insert a pair of antithetical comments. He'll say something like, you know, the current topic under discussion would actually have come before the topic that preceded this discussion. But then he'll tell us that his ordering of the material is a result of divine unveiling or kashf, and that is not the result of his own intellectual efforts at systematizing. So the kind of anti-systematic spirit, if we can call it that in Ibn ʿArabī's writings, and indeed the vast ocean of symbolism, as you mentioned, visionary experiences, arcane kind of mysterious references, that was clearly imbibed by Qūnawī, interestingly enough. And Qūnawī was, of course, very much a philosopher in a way that Ibn ʿArabī was not. And so Ibn ʿArabī trains Qūnawī. He is a stepson. And the same individual ends up becoming so different in so many ways from Ibn ʿArabī. I mean, Qūnawī, you know, we have, for example, a handwritten copy in his own handwriting of Suhrawardī's Ḥikmat al- ishrāq, Philosophy of Illumination. And he initiates, of course, a very serious correspondence with Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī after having read Ṭūsī’s already famous commentary of Pan-Avicenna's Isharāt

So Qūnawī represents a unique turning point in the history of philosophical Sufism in a way that Ibn ʿArabī does not, because we have here for the first time a first-rate philosopher, a theologian, but somebody who is trained by none other than Ibn ʿArabī himself. And he's got kind of a foot in the peripatetic and the Ishrāqi traditions, and he's also, for better or worse, we can call him an Akbarian or someone who belonged to the so-called school of Ibn ʿArabī. And Qūnawī's own writings are quite different from Ibn ʿArabī's often in terms of, you know, their modes of expression, their form, and even to some extent their content. They're far more systematic, logical, they're ordered, they're less, if you like, baroque in style. And there's an element of the visionary there, but we now encounter a visionary who kind of crafts Sufi discourse to sound more logically rigorous and more philosophically inclined in terms of the language, too. It can certainly be said that Qūnawī is the single individual most responsible for the more reified kind of abstract manner of expression that characterizes the school of Ibn ʿArabī. And he intended to emphasize, as did every major follower in the school after him, especially Dāwūd al- Qayṣarī, he wouldn't necessarily have given pride of place to certain aspects of Ibn ʿArabī's thought, whereas Qūnawī does. And in many ways this is interesting, because Qūnawī is commenting on in many ways what is important or what he finds to be important in Ibn ʿArabī's own articulation of his vision of things. And Qūnawī's necessarily leaving out a lot of key kind of mythological, cosmological discussions you find in Ibn ʿArabī. Things that Ibn ʿArabī would say over 30, 40 pages in the Futūḥāt, Qūnawī will have a one-page dense explanation of what is going on there, and in a language that I think his intention is to really speak to audiences whose ears, so to speak, were not as well trained as his were in understanding his stepfather. 15.15 

PA: Right, so sort of "Ibn ʿArabī for Dummies"! 

MR: Yeah, in many ways a kind of dumbed down version of Ibn ʿArabī. In fact, a teacher of mine once said to me, you know, we should stop calling it the school of Ibn ʿArabī, we should just call it the school of Qūnawī, because largely all the followers after Qūnawī, or after Ibn ʿArabī, are in one way or another influenced by Qūnawī. And he's really seen as kind of like the filter to interpret Ibn ʿArabī. Even Jāmī, the famous Persian poet who died in 1492, who was very much a follower of the school of Ibn ʿArabī, says in one of his books that if you want to understand Ibn ʿArabī, you can only do it through reading Qūnawī. So you kind of have this acknowledgement, even into the 15th, 16th century, that this person is really the prism through which Ibn ʿArabī is to be interpreted. 16.05 

PA: So let me ask you about a couple of the philosophical issues that seem really central, I think, both for Ibn ʿArabī and Qūnawī, and of course, they're both going to have to do with God and God's relationship to the world, since it doesn't get more central than that. And maybe we can go straight to what might be the most obvious worry that someone could have about these philosophical Sufis, which is that they seem to be describing the created universe as nothing but a manifestation, maybe an illusory manifestation, of God. And so this might make you think that they're some kind of monists - in other words, they actually think only God exists, or maybe they're pantheists - in other words, they think that everything is God. Do you think they can be defended against these charges? 

MR: Ah, now that is a trick question. In a sense, the easiest way to reply to your question would be to say yes, and since there are plenty of passages in Ibn ʿArabī in particular that can be read as exclusively a kind of form of monism or pantheism or panentheism, or even as something that brings together one or all of these "isms", like pantheistic monism or something like that. The problem here, as I see it, really has to do with whether these kinds of terms, reductive as they must necessarily be, can really do justice to Ibn ʿArabī's vision, which stresses in the same breath really, oneness and unity, but there's alongside that multiplicity, otherness and even relationality. 17.40 

So let's take, for example, the question of pantheism. Does Ibn ʿArabī say that there's an essential identity or some kind of identity with God in the cosmos? Yes, he certainly does speak like this. That was enough, of course, to drive Ibn Taymiyya mad. I mean he liked Ibn ʿArabī to a point, but after a while he just lost patience with him, and then he decides to refute him and called him an incarnationist and all kinds of things. He was an ittiḥād - someone who didn't really distinguish between the creator and the creature. Ibn ʿArabī would tell us that that does not in any way explain the entire picture. So while he'd say, yes, that is true, God and the cosmos are one, or something like this, God as identified with the world or being in the world, or part of the world, he'd say bespeaks God's givenness or his revealedness or manifestness in the cosmos, which points up to what he called his immanence or tashbīh. 18.40 

And at the same time, Ibn ʿArabī places just as much, even more, actually, emphasis on how the cosmos is not God in any sense of the term, how God is so utterly beyond and distinct from the world and stands above it by virtue of his inaccessibility or hiddenness or non-revealed face, if you like. And that points up his transcendence or his tanzīh. So Ibn ʿArabī commonly refers to the cosmos as he, not he, huwa lā huwa. And that does away with the kind of simplistic either-or kind of scenario in which the explanation of the cosmic situation and God's relationship to it tries to trap God and is it like this or is it like that? - huwa lā huwa seeks to really retain both. I would be very cautious to use any of these terms - pantheism, monism, so on and so forth - if we were to use them, we would have to add a great degree of qualification. And by the time these qualifications can be made, you know - if you want to say Ibn ʿArabī is a monist, sure, but then all the other stuff, the very terms in question would then really not carry much weight because we would have to add so many caveats and so many explanations, we would have to really gloss these terms that they really just lose much of their significance. 

So I mean, from this perspective, even a term that is used often to explain the perspective of Ibn ʿArabī and his followers, waḥdat al-wujūd, or the oneness of being, even that phrase, I mean, it is something that Ibn ʿArabī doesn't use himself, and it only becomes a technical term three or four decades after his death. But that term also has certain major limitations to it, because it can be perceived as emphasizing only the he aspect of the he-not-he formula. And that is certainly how Ibn Taymiyya understood the term, and many other later detractors of Ibn ʿArabī as well. For example, Shaykh Aḥmad Sirhindī, the famous Indian Sufi who died in 1624. 20.50 

PA: It seems like what you're saying is basically that Ibn ʿArabī gives us this interesting dialectical idea where the world is both God and not God. 

MR: Yeah 

PA: And so it would be overly simplistic to just take one side of this polarity. But on the other hand, I mean, as philosophers, we're probably not too happy with someone saying, well, the solution is to just contradict yourself all the time. And so it seemed to me, and this is something I talked a bit about in the episode on him, but I wanted to get you to say something more about it. It seemed to me that one of the most promising moves he makes to explain this position without just saying, you know, P and not-P are both true, is to describe the world in terms of divine attributes or the names of God. 

MR: Yes 

PA: Because it seems like a name plausibly is both in a sense the same thing as the named thing and in a sense not the same as the named thing. But on the other hand, it is hard to understand how something like a name could metaphysically be the same as the created universe. So do you think the point he's trying to make there, is that more of an analogy? So is he saying that created things relate to God the way that names might relate to the bearer of the name, or is it actually that we are literally the names of God as created things? 22.20 

MR: This too is a trick question. You know, Ibn ʿArabī's most common way of speaking about what the names are, or really what they're not, is by speaking to them as relationships. So this is something that he does which seems, at least from one perspective, quite revolutionary in the history of Islamic thought, because, I mean, the way we speak about the divine names in classical Islamic theology was to maintain that they somehow inhere in God, or God's essence, what they've called qāʾima bi-dhātihi, but not in a way that kind of gave them independent ontological status such that they could be said to be superadded to it. 

So for many medieval Muslim theologians and presumably some philosophers, the objective kind of ontological status of the divine names was never really called into question. It was a given, even if their modality could not be easily understood or explained. Ibn ʿArabī comes on the scene and he vehemently rejects this common type of picture of the divine names. He says that the divine names do not inhere in God in any way, and he says that they're not ontological entities, which is like one of his main points, and he really tries to explain things from that perspective. He says they're not umūr wujūdiyya or ontological things. So instead he says that they are, technically speaking, relationships, nisab, between what we can call God as revealed or manifest and the objects of God's knowledge that do enter into concrete existence, so what Ibn ʿArabī and the later tradition call loci or self-disclosure or manifestation, maẓāhir in Arabic. 24.00 

So the divine names come about as a result of God's self-disclosure or manifestation, and they thus make the God-world relationship for Ibn ʿArabī possible. Yet the cosmos is nothing other than a conglomeration of the divine name, as we can say, as displayed through the existential aspects of God's knowledge. So the universe is impregnated ultimately with the divine attributes, and the very multiplicity in the cosmos, therefore as we see it, because it manifests the attributes, obviously point to the divine names. So by the same token, since the divine names are relationships for Ibn ʿArabī and not actual ontological entities, the multiplicity in the cosmos is in actuality not any real kind of plurality. So this kind of move that Ibn ʿArabī is making here, where he's emphasizing their reality on one level and then because they are relationships, they are ultimately unreal, has posed the greatest, I think, philosophical challenge for his later interpreters. How do we understand these names? Because the names allow for multiplicity to emerge, and at the same time, they are paradoxically the very reason for the world's relative unreality. 

PA: So actually I find that very helpful philosophically, because I mean, if the names really denote relationships or relations, it does seem like a relation is a real thing without being an entity in its own right, which is kind of what he wants, right? 23.35 

MR: Yes. 

PA: So let me ask you something rather different now, just about the later historical influence of Ibn ʿArabī. And actually, maybe we can start with a contemporary of Qūnawī, namely Rūmī, who's maybe the most famous Sufi, even more famous than Ibn ʿArabī because of his poetry and the popularity of his literary outputs. Qūnawī and Rūmī were friends - they are even buried near each other in Konya - and it seems a little bit hard to wrap our minds around, right? So Qūnawī is, as you were saying before, systematic, even sort of technical approach to Sufism, Rūmī - this kind of ecstatic poet. So how do we reconcile two such different authors as being two outgrowths of the same Sufi tree, as it were? 

MR: Right. Well, that is, again, another very, very important question. There's a really nice anecdote, and there are all kinds of anecdotes in which Qūnawī figures. But this one in the later tradition, tells us that one day Qūnawī and Rūmī are sitting together in Kunya, and one of Rūmī's students comes up to him and asks him a question that had been bothering him. And Rūmī gives him, in characteristic fashion, a couplet in Persian, and the student is happy, and he walks away, and he's very pleased with his answer. So Qūnawī turns to Rūmī, and he says to him, "how is it that you can make such difficult ideas seem so simple?" And to this Rūmī responds, "how is it that you can make such simple ideas sound so difficult?" 

So what is important to keep in mind here is that neither Rūmī nor Qūnawī saw a problem with each other's different modes of expression. I mean, Rumi's thought evinces some of the theoretical, philosophical tendencies which characterize Qūnawī. I mean, Rūmī was a Māturīdī theologian also. But Qūnawī's thought also evinces some of the more poetic tendencies that we find in Rūmī. And judging from the plain sense of Rumi's reply to Qūnawī, he probably did think that Qūnawī was unnecessarily complicating things, if you like. So having said that, there is a caveat here that we need to introduce, at least where Rūmī is concerned. He is often seen as kind of being an anti-intellectual or anti- philosophical person. I mean, there's plenty of verses in his poetry to corroborate that kind of a position. 28.10 The most common verse, surely, is the one in which he says that "the leg of the philosophers is wooden. A wooden leg is terribly un-sturdy." 

 

پای استدلالیان چوبین بود  
پای چوبین سخت بی تمکین بود

 

But one contemporary scholar, at least one that I've seen, emphasizes here that Rūmī doesn't say the philosophers don't have a leg to stand on. He says that they do, but that it is just wooden. So it is not enough to allow them to, in Rūmī's language, fly up to the heavenly imperium. So in order to do this, Rūmī would emphasize love. And that is, of course, the thing that he's known best for. But I get the feeling that Qūnawī would not necessarily disagree. I think that ultimately they see their goals essentially similar, even if their modes of expression and intellectual types really were not the same. 

PA: Maybe we could even say that, in a sense, they take on two different sides of Ibn ʿArabī's thought, because obviously Ibn ʿArabī is full of poetic imagery. And also, you know, there's the earlier sort of tradition of love poetry in Sufism, so Rūmī is taking that on. And Qūnawī is taking on the more technical, philosophically influenced aspects of Ibn ʿArabī. 

MR: Yes. 

PA: And how appropriate that he was uniting these two apparently contradictory tendencies in himself. 

MR: Yes, yes, exactly. 

PA: Just one last question, looking ahead a bit to where we're going in future episodes. Obviously Sufism has this massive influence across the Islamic world, really down to the present day. But can you say something a little bit more specifically about philosophical Sufism? So what was the geographical spread of philosophical Sufism? I mean, obviously we've been talking about people who wrote in Persian, as well as Arabic. So certainly there's this philosophical Sufi tradition in Persia. What about, for example, in India or elsewhere in the Islamic world in the, let's say, the early modern period? 30.15 

MR: Right. So what's particularly interesting here is that, like you said, the philosophical Sufism or Sufism of a more kind of theoretical kind really spreads throughout the eastern lands of Islam, like wildfire. I mean, this is a phenomenon for at least over the next 500 years. You have people in the Ottoman period, for example, writing in sometimes Persian, but often Ottoman Turkish, like Ismāʿīl ʿAnqarawī, who's directly bringing together Ibn ʿArabī's thought, and actually he was a commentator on Rūmī, too. And the Ottoman world was so vast that you have authors in that universe who lived in places like today, would be Bosnia, Turkey, Syria, so very, very vast geographical expanse, of course Persia and Central Asia. 31.10 

In India, where the school of Ibn ʿArabī in particular, had a very important second wind, if you like, the writings tended to be in Persian, because most Indian Sufis in the later period wrote in Persian. And there the aforementioned Shaykh Aḥmad al- Sirhindī was very important for at least responding to Ibn ʿArabī, even though he wasn't necessarily always on board with his central thesis. Shāh Walī Allāh al- Dihlawī was a major figure also who was working in the Indian context and who had a very important role to play in bringing Ibn ʿArabī's thought and bringing philosophical Sufism into something like a more mainstream intellectual discourse, because he was a very well-respected scholar who went to the ʿulamāʾ class as well. 32.00 

So India's case is interesting, and many other minor figures in India, Khwāja Khurd, Muḥibb Allāh Ilāhbādī, people like this, all of whom their writings really evince a very deep kind of penetration, if you like, of the central tenets of the school of Ibn ʿArabī, and who, like Qūnawī and like his later followers, all try their hand at systematizing this worldview. And what happens in India is you have many practical Sufi manuals written by Sufi masters, you know, guides of how to get there, so to speak, but which conscientiously engage the school of Ibn ʿArabī. 32.40 

One of the most interesting later developments in which philosophical Sufism has yet another sphere of influence is actually in China, which is quite surprising. I mean, research into this is only being done today in a more sustained fashion. But, you know, by the 17th century you have very important Chinese ʿulamāʾ or Chinese scholars, Wang Daiyu, Liu Zhi, people like this, who in order to attempt to explain Islam to their Chinese counterparts, most of whom were Neo-Confucians, drew on the writings of Ibn ʿArabī and his followers, usually through Persian translation. But they did so by crafting the Chinese language now to speak the language of Neo- Confucianism. So you have Chinese Muslim authors drawing on Ibn ʿArabī's ideas, but recasting them in Chinese in such a way that a Neo-Confucian could kind of understand it, and also some of their Buddhist colleagues as well. And that is a trend that in many ways characterized the later intellectual life of the Chinese Muslim. In many ways it is also symptomatic of what's happening in North America and Europe in the 20th century and even into now the 21st century, where you have many authors who for one reason or another espouse the cause of Ibn ʿArabī or the school of Ibn ʿArabī or philosophical Sufism or the wedding of philosophical Sufism, and who seek to refashion even the English language, for example, to speak these things, or French. 34.20 

So that is the influence of the school of Ibn ʿArabī on Sufism proper. But it also has a very important sustained influence on the discipline of Islamic philosophy as well. And this is most clearly seen, of course, in the writings of Mullā Ṣadrā. The entire school of Isfahan read into, again, the 20th century. Even until today you have many authors in Iran who are followers of Mullā Ṣadrā or espouse his views, but who have a vested interest in Ibn ʿArabī. So in Mullā Ṣadrā you have the wedding of several different strands of Islamic thought - Shīʿite theology of course, a very deep engagement with the philosophical tradition, and a response to Ibn ʿArabī obviously - and he takes Ibn ʿArabī extremely seriously to the point that he's even himself accused at some points in his career of being too pro-Ibn ʿArabī or too pro-Sunni. 

So all of these trends, if we look at them together in terms of the geographical dispersion of the tradition, we have a very, very wide expanse in which Ibn ʿArabī's ideas and the systematization and articulation of his ideas go into so many different modes, so to speak. You have them in practical manuals. Now they're in Chinese, speaking Confucian Chinese. They're in philosophical texts, of course, the poetic tradition is greatly indebted to Ibn ʿArabī, and actually, ʿAyn al-Quḍāt and Ibn ʿArabī actually meet up in the Persian poetic tradition as well, where you have ʿAyn al- Quḍāt speaking theoretically about many of these ideas in Persian, and then Ibn ʿArabī's school articulating some of the same ideas in Arabic and then in Persian. And then you have poets like ʿIraqī, who died in the 13th century, or Maḥmūd Shabistarī, who died in the following century, trying to bring them together now within the medium of the poetic tradition. And so Persian poetry also is given a new life because of the school of Ibn ʿArabī. 

PA: Thanks. that is really remarkable and amazing. I mean, obviously, the later history of Sufism is so vast that it could be the subject for its own series of podcasts. So someone should really do that, Mohammed. 

MR: Yes. 

PA: Just saying! 

MR: Oh, we're taking hints! 

PA: Right. Exactly. Thank you very much. You also mentioned a lot of things that I'll be getting on to look at, so philosophy in the Ottoman tradition, in the Mughal period of India, and especially, I guess, the Safavids. But more proximately, next week I'll be moving on to something very different, which will actually be the ongoing tradition of logic in this period. So I hope the audience will join me for that. For now, I'll just thank you, Mohammed, for coming on the podcast. 

MR: Thank you very much for having me.